|
|
|
Aristotle Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.), the son of a physician,
was the student of Plato
from approximately 367 B.C.E. until his mentor's death in 348/347. After
carrying on philosophical and scientific investigations
elsewhere in the Greek world and serving as the tutor to Alexander the
Great, he returned to Athens in 335 B.C.E. to found the Lyceum, a major
philosophical center, which he used as his base for prolific investigations
into many areas of philosophy. Much of Aristotle's published work, including
all his carefully written and polished essays, has disappeared. The studies
that have survived, including the Poetics, have come down to us in a
fragmented form, which suggests that they may be lecture notes (of Aristotle
himself or of a student attending his lectures), outlines for future works
to be published, or summaries of already published works. There has long
been speculation that the original Poetics comprised two books, our
extant Poetics and a lost second book that supposedly dealt with
comedy and/or katharsis. No firm evidence for
the existence of this second book has been adduced, but Richard Janko has
argued that evidence for its content can be recovered. Our knowledge of the
text of the Poetics depends principally on a manuscript of the tenth
or eleventh century and a second manuscript dating from the fourteenth
century. These sources are supplemented by a thirteenth-century Latin
translation of the text by William of Moerbeke, a tenth-century Arabic
translation, and a fragment of an earlier Syriac translation.
On a number of subjects Aristotle developed positions that significantly
differed from those of his teacher. We very clearly note this profound
difference of opinion with Plato and, indeed, observe the overt correction
of his erstwhile master in Aristotle's literary and aesthetic theories. As
is well known, Plato's negative view of art stems from, first, his view that
its essential character as mimesis forces upon it a profound
ontological alienation from true reality and, second, his observation that
artistic mimesis addresses itself essentially to the emotional, rather than
the intellectual, aspect of the human psyche and thus dangerously subverts
the character of both the individual and the state.
The principal source of our knowledge of Aristotle's aesthetic and
literary theory is the Poetics, but important supplementary
information is found in other treatises, chiefly the Rhetoric, the
Politics, and the Nicomachean Ethics. As expressed in these
works, Aristotelian aesthetics directly contradicts Plato's negative view of
art by establishing a potent intellectual role for artistic mimesis. For
Aristotle, mimesis describes a process involving the use by different art
forms of different means of representation, different manners of
communicating that representation to an audience, and different levels of
moral and ethical behavior as objects of the artistic representation. Thus
Aristotle distinguishes between tragedy and comedy essentially on the basis
of the fact that the former represents "noble" or "morally good" agents,
while the latter portrays "ignoble" or "morally defective" characters. All
forms of mimesis, however, including tragedy and comedy, come into existence
because of a fundamental intellectual impulse felt by all human beings. In
the Metaphysics Aristotle describes this impulse as humanity's
"desire to know," and in chapter 4 of the Poetics he identifies it
with the essential pleasure we human beings find in all mimesis, the
pleasure of "learning and inference." In chapter 14, moreover, Aristotle
states that the tragic poet must provide pleasure from pity and fear through
mimesis, thus alerting us again to the intellectual pleasure generated by
tragic mimesis. In chapter 9 he asserts that poetry "is more philosophical
and more significant than history" because its goal is the representation of
that which is universal, while history has the expression of the particular
as its object. In this emphasis on the intellectual and philosophical
dimensions of mimesis, Aristotle directly contradicts Plato's derogation of
art as an inferior appeal to human emotions.
Aristotle's main focus in the Poetics is on the genre of tragedy,
but he also makes important comments on comedy and epic. His fundamental
theoretical stipulations about the essential nature of mimesis must apply to
all genres of literature (tragedy, comedy, epic, etc.) and all other forms
of mimesis (music, dance, painting, sculpture, etc.). These basic
stipulations are that mimesis is fundamental to our nature as human beings,
that human beings are the most imitative of all creatures, that first
learning experiences take place through mimesis, and that all human beings
take pleasure in mimesis because all find "learning and inference"
essentially pleasant. Since the focus of the Poetics is mainly on
literary mimesis, it is necessary for us to concentrate on Aristotle's
understanding of the way this aspect of mimetic activity leads to the
intellectual pleasure he assigns to art.
Aristotle specifies that the function of literary mimesis is to represent
a complete and unified action consisting of a beginning, middle, and end
linked by necessary and probable causes. The magnitude of such a work is to
be such as may easily be held in the memory and yet remain quite clear to an
audience. If the beginning, middle, and end of an action are clearly and
persuasively motivated, the conditions will be present for "learning and
inference" to occur (ch. 4). What could interfere with the accomplishment of
this goal are "simple" and "episodic" plots, the former occurring without
reversal of fortune (peripeteia) and recognition of some unknown
person or fact (anagnorisis) and the latter occurring when the
sequence of episodes fails to obey the laws of necessity and probability. To
serve the goal of persuasive lucidity, both reversal and recognition must
arise naturally out of the structure of the plot because, as Aristotle says,
"it makes a great difference if something happens because of something else
or merely after it" (ch. 10).
According to Aristotle, the emotions represented and evoked in tragedy
are pity and fear. He defines pity as the emotion we feel toward someone who
has suffered undeserved misfortune, and fear as the emotion we feel when we
realize that the one who suffers this misfortune is someone like ourselves.
Now, pity and fear, when we experience them in actual life, are painful
feelings, but when they occur in tragic mimesis they are integrated into a
structure that has the production of intellectual pleasure as its goal.
Aristotle connects the effective evocation of pity and fear to the nature of
the hamartia, the tragic mistake or flaw,
attributed to the protagonist.
Pity and fear arise only when someone who is very much like ourselves,
that is, neither unqualifiedly virtuous nor deeply flawed, falls from
happiness to misery because of a hamartia or even a great hamartia. Earlier
disputes about the meaning of "hamartia" in this context in the Poetics
have given way to an evolving interpretive consensus. It was not uncommon
formerly to identify Aristotelian hamartia with a "moral flaw" and to
attempt to find in the plot of Sophocles' Oedipus Tyrannus
justification for this view. Some critics in the past have identified
Oedipus's hamartia as his violent anger. Thus Philip Whaley Harsh comments
that "the pre-eminently good and just man does not fly into a fury when a
carriage crowds him from the road, and he does not commit murder
indiscriminately even when he is lashed by the driver" (48). Perceptive
interpretations of that play (Sophocles himself provides an eloquent defense
of Oedipus in the Oedipus at Colonus) and of the term "hamartia,"
however, offer a persuasive refutation of this view. Kurt
von Fritz represents this line of thinking when he
argues persuasively that no blame can attach to Oedipus for defending
himself against an attack by a party of strangers in an isolated locale
where no other protection was available. It now seems clear that since the
protagonist of Aristotle's "best tragedy," the tragedy of pity and fear,
must be a "good" (spoudaios) human being, the required hamartia must
be some kind of intellectual mistake that cannot subvert the dignity of
someone "like ourselves." D. W. Lucas defines it as "the blindness which is
part of the human condition" (307), and P. van Braam describes it as "the
insufficiency of the human mind to cope with the mysterious complex of the
world" (271).
The key term, and the most controversial one, in Aristotle's theory of
artistic mimesis is katharsis. The term has fascinated and troubled
scholars at least since the sixteenth century, and the abundant interpretive
literature on the concept continues to increase. Three major lines of
interpretation emerge, representing the medical, moral, and cognitive views
of katharsis.
The medical interpretation, deriving most influentially from the work of
Jacob Bernays, bases itself on Aristotle's use of
katharsis in the Politics (1341b36-1342a16) to describe a process
through which music effects a medical cure by purging a pathological excess
of emotion. Bernays assumed that precisely this type of therapeutic
katharsis takes place in tragedy. According to this interpretation, the
audience must be assumed to suffer from an excess of pity and fear, to seek
a remedy for this excess through the homeopathic cure afforded by exposure
to additional pity and fear in tragedy, and to experience pleasure because
of the relief felt when the cure has been achieved. There are obvious
difficulties with such an interpretation, which requires that artistic
mimesis be identified with a therapeutic process. There is no evidence in
the Poetics to support the view that the essential goal of mimesis is
therapeutic; indeed, there is very strong evidence leading to a quite
different conclusion.
The interpretation of katharsis as a form of moral purification is
identified with the great German dramatist and critic
G. E. Lessing, whose view, often combined with aspects of the
purgation theory, has influenced a number of subsequent critics. This
interpretation is based on a passage in the Nicomachean Ethics
(1106b16-23) that asserts that our goal must be to experience emotions
virtuously, that is, in accordance with the proper mean between excess and
deficiency. The purgation theory views pity and fear as pathological states
that must be removed, while the purification interpretation makes the
experiencing of these emotions in the proper amount and way a sign of
virtue. The idea of katharsis as purification in this moral sense,
like purgation, has no supporting evidence in the text of the Poetics.
It is only when we turn to the cognitive interpretation of katharsis
that we find explicit supporting evidence in the Poetics. This
evidence has been most fully explored by Kurt von Fritz, Pedro Laín Entralgo,
and Leon Golden. First, we recall the important passage in chapter 4
(1448b4-17), where Aristotle tells us that mimesis is by nature a part of
human experience from childhood on, that it is the basis of our first
learning experiences, and that all human beings derive pleasure from it.
This pleasure does not derive from the nature of the object represented in
the mimesis, for as Aristotle says, we take pleasure in imitated
objects such as "despised wild animals and corpses," which would cause us
pain if we saw them in reality. For Aristotle, the pleasure arising from
mimesis is the pleasure of learning and inference, which "is not only most
pleasant to philosophers" but pleasant to all others as well, though in a
more limited way. Aristotle further supports the cognitive nature and goals
of mimesis when he attributes to poetry in chapter 9 a philosophical
dimension arising from its capacity to express universals rather than
particulars. In chapter 14 (1453b8-14) he tells us that "it is necessary for
the poet to provide pleasure from pity and fear through mimesis" and so once
again calls attention to the cognitive function of mimesis, whose essential
pleasure we know to be "learning and inference."
The theme of katharsis as a cognitive process is very much a
product of twentieth-century thought about this concept. Translations
denoting "purgation" and "purification" dominate the interpretations of
katharsis from the sixteenth century to the end of the nineteenth
century, which Ingram Bywater collected in an appendix
to his important edition of the Poetics. Donald Keesey, in his 1979
survey of twentieth-century interpretations of katharsis, notes the
appearance of various nuances of "clarification" in more recent analysis.
Matthias Luserke, in his anthology of nineteenth- and twentieth-century
documents relating to the interpretation of katharsis, includes two
essays advocating the "clarification" theory of katharsis in a "pure"
or modified form. The cognitive view of katharsis is now gaining
momentum as an alternative to the traditional interpretations of "purgation"
and "purification."
Gerald Else, although he never accepted an intellectual interpretation of
katharsis, opened up the way for such an interpretation by his sharp
attack on the purgation theory. He called attention to the fact that such a
theory "presupposes that we come to the tragic drama (unconsciously, if you
will) as patients to be cured, relieved, restored to psychic health. But
there is not a word to support this in the Poetics, not a hint that
the end of drama is to cure or alleviate pathological states" (440). Else,
in his turn, defined katharsis as "the purification of the tragic act
by the demonstration that its motive was not miaron [morally
polluted]" (439). As a consequence of such a determination the audience is
permitted to experience pity for the tragic hero. In spite of Else's
reluctance to accept an interpretation of katharsis as
"clarification," his view does require katharsis to be based on some
form of cognitive process, since the judgment that an act was not morally
polluted must begin with the intellectual analysis of the circumstances
under which the act was performed.
The cognitive view of katharsis is supported both by the analysis
of the internal argument of the Poetics and by arguments based on the
way words are used in ancient and modern psychotherapy. Both Pedro Laín
Entralgo, a historian of ancient medicine, and Bennett
Simon, a practicing psychiatrist, offer us a persuasive insight into the way
words in literary contexts affect an audience. Laín Entralgo notes that in
the mind of the spectator at a tragedy there is a "deep demand for
expression and clarification of the human destiny" (230), and he notes that
any emotional and somatic pleasure felt in tragedy is a secondary resultant
of a primary intellectual pleasure. In regard to such emotional and somatic
pleasure he says, "Previous to it and determining its genesis were and had
to be those [pleasures] pertaining to the good order of the soul, both of
affective character (having to do with the thymos) and of intellective
nature (concerning dianoia)" (236). Simon argues that tragedy
should bring some altered and new sense of what one is and who he is in
relation to those around him . . . the audience acquires a new sense of the
possibilities in being human and in coming to terms with the forces that are
more powerful than any one individual. In therapy we also expect an enlarged
view of the possibilities that are open in relationships to the self and
others. Thus good therapy and good theater have in common a set of inner
processes. (144) |
|
Simon, however,
correctly understands, as the defenders of the purgation theory of
katharsis do not, the essential difference between therapy and
aesthetics. He notes that "theater is not, and was not for the Greeks,
primarily intended to be therapy for especially disturbed or distressed
people. It was expected to provide a certain form of pleasure, even in Greek
culture, and was an integral part of the paideia (education in the
broadest sense) of each Athenian" (144-45). It is only--and this is a matter
of very great importance--the verbal triggering of intellectual and
emotional responses that the two processes share in common. Evidence for
the interpretation of katharsis as "intellectual clarification" based
on the internal argument of the Poetics has been presented by Leon
Golden, Martha Nussbaum, and Christian
Wagner, who have suggested ways of expanding or
modifying this interpretation. Nussbaum argues for katharsis as
"clarification," but a clarification that does not depend exclusively on the
intellect but could be generated by emotion as well. Wagner maintains that
the clarification involved in tragedy is limited to ethical issues.
While the principal subject of the Poetics is tragedy, important
comments are also made in the work about comedy and, to a lesser extent,
about epic. As mentioned above, there has long been speculation about the
existence of a lost second book of the Poetics dealing with
Aristotle's theory of comedy. In the absence of that book, if it ever
existed, scholars have had recourse to two sources as a basis for
establishing Aristotle's views about the nature of comedy. One of these is
the Tractatus Coislinianus, a treatise contained in an early
tenth-century manuscript whose value and authenticity have been subjected to
strong scholarly disagreement. Bywater called it a "sorry fabrication" and
cited Bernays's view of it as a travesty (xxii). Janko has defended its
value as a source for Aristotelian comic theory. The other source is the
Poetics itself and other indisputably genuine Aristotelian texts that
provide us with enough reliable data to permit us to reconstruct most, if
not all, of Aristotle's theory of comedy.
We must first recall that for Aristotle all forms of mimesis, including
tragic and comic mimesis, have as their goal the evocation of intellectual
pleasure. Thus, comic mimesis must meet all of the stringent requirements
set forth for tragic mimesis in terms of the persuasive lucidity that is the
necessary prerequisite for the climactic experience of "learning and
inference" required of all mimesis. Tragedy, we have been told, aims at the
katharsis of pity and fear and thus must represent the actions of
"good" or "noble" (in a moral or ethical sense) human beings. Comedy,
Aristotle tells us, represents the opposite kind of character, which we can
designate as "base" or "ignoble." Moreover, comedy represents such
characters, not in regard to every kind of vice, but in
regard to the ridiculous, a subdivision of the general category of moral and
physical deformity. For the ridiculous is some error and deformity which is
not painful or destructive--the example which immediately comes to mind is
the comic mask which is ugly and distorted but which does not cause pain. (Poetics
ch. 5)
|
|
We can learn a great
deal about the nature of the "base" characters represented in comedy from
the discussion of human vices and virtues in the Nicomachean Ethics.
Thus, a great deal of what we must know about the means, objects, and manner
of comic mimesis is provided to us by available, authentic Aristotelian
texts. What these texts do not provide is a discussion of the emotions,
analogous to pity and fear in tragedy, that are aroused in comedy. What we
do know with certainty is that the emotion or emotions aroused in comedy
must be related to the representation of "base" human beings involved in
action designated by Aristotle as "ridiculous" and thus must be opposed in
some way to the emotions evoked by the "noble" characters represented in
tragedy. On the basis of this authentically Aristotelian view of the nature
of comedy and tragedy, we can at least speculate reasonably about the
emotions evoked in comedy. Since for Aristotle tragedy and comedy are
directly opposed to each other in terms of the character and action they
represent, we may ask whether Aristotle anywhere designates the emotion that
is opposed to pity and fear. Here we do have information that could help us
in developing a hypothesis about comic emotion. In the Rhetoric
Aristotle addresses the question of pity and its opposed emotional
experience. He states there that the direct opposite of pity is what may be
called "righteous indignation" (nemesan), which is a feeling of pain
at undeserved good fortune in the same way that pity is a feeling of pain at
undeserved misfortune. Edward M. Cope analyzes the concept of righteous
indignation (expressed by the Greek terms nemesan and nemesis)
as follows: |
|
According to
Aristotle's definition of nemesis "a feeling of pain at undeserved good
fortune" it represents the "righteous indignation" arising from a sense of
the claims of justice and desert, which is aroused in us by the
contemplation of success without merit, and a consequent pleasure in the
punishment of one who is thus undeservedly prosperous. (2:108)
|
|
We can say that
both Old Comedy and New Comedy provide significant instances of "base"
characters behaving in a ridiculous manner and achieving, at least
temporarily, undeserved success. At the end of the comedy these characters
regularly meet with deserved punishment. Thus the idea of righteous
indignation alluded to in the Rhetoric as the opposite of pity does
bear a clear relationship to the action of comedy. Calling attention to this
suggestive idea, however, is probably as far as we should go in our
speculation on Aristotle's view of the comic emotions. In the final
chapter of the Poetics Aristotle compares tragedy and epic, both of
which represent "noble" characters. He notes that tragedy contains all of
the elements in epic and additional ones unique to itself. The most
important way, however, in which tragedy differs from, and is superior to,
epic is in its much more compact structure. Aristotle sees the much greater
length of epic, with its main plot and subplots, as an impediment to the
lucid and persuasive unfolding of the poem's theme. He judges tragedy to be
superior because its carefully orchestrated incidents, bound together from
beginning to middle to end by psychological and aesthetic necessity and
probability, achieve tragedy's mimetic goal more effectively than is
possible for epic, with its looser and more cumbrous structure. Here again,
at the end of the Poetics, Aristotle reveals the central role
cognitive pleasure plays in his aesthetic theory.
Aristotle has exerted a large and enduring influence on literary
criticism and aesthetic theory. New translations and new interpretations of
his work in this area regularly appear. In part these new contributions
continue interpretive disagreements that have existed for centuries, but
recent scholarship has also been moving toward the resolution of some
longstanding controversies and the deeper illumination of others. We can be
certain that in changing aesthetic landscapes, where the expectations for
criticism may undergo radical transformations, the voice of Aristotle will
always be heard, asserting authoritatively that the critic's essential duty
is to investigate the way the organic structure of a work of art leads us to
a universalizing epiphany involving the highest human pleasure, the pleasure
of learning and inference about significant human actions.
Leon Golden
|
|
Notes and Bibliography |
|
See also
Chicago Critics,
Classical Theory and Criticism,
Drama Theory,
Medieval Theory and Criticism,
and Renaissance Theory and
Criticism.
Samuel Henry Butcher, Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art, with a
Critical Text and Translation of the "Poetics" (1902); Ingram Bywater,
Aristotle on the Art of Poetry (1909); Lane Cooper, An
Aristotelian Theory of Comedy (1922), Aristotle on the Art of Poetry
(1947); Edward M. Cope and John Edwin Sandys, The Rhetoric of Aristotle,
with an adaptation of the "Poetics" and a Translation of the "Tractatus
Coislinianus" (3 vols., 1877, reprint, 1988); Roselyne Dupont-Roc and
Jean Lallot, Aristote: La Poétique (1980); Gerald Frank Else,
Aristotle's "Poetics": The Argument (1957); Leon Golden and O. B.
Hardison, Jr., Aristotle's Poetics: A Translation and Commentary for
Students of Literature (1981); D. W. Lucas, Aristotle: "Poetics"
(1968).
P. van Braam, "Aristotle's Use of Hamartia" Classical Quarterly 6
(1912); R. D. Dawe, "Some Reflections on Ate and Hamartia,"
Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 72 (1967); Gerald Frank Else,
Plato and Aristotle on Poetry (1986); Kurt von Fritz, Antike und
moderne Tragödie (1962); Leon Golden, "Aristotle on Comedy," Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 42 (1984), "Catharsis," Transactions
of the American Philological Association 93 (1962), "The Clarification
Theory of Katharsis," Hermes 104 (1976), "Comic Pleasure," Hermes
115 (1987); Stephen Halliwell, Aristotle's "Poetics" (1986); Philip
Whaley Harsh, "Hamartia Again," Transactions of the American Philological
Association 76 (1945); Malcolm Heath, "Aristotelian Comedy,"
Classical Quarterly 39 (1989), The Poetics of Greek Tragedy
(1987); Richard Janko, Aristotle on Comedy: Towards a Reconstruction of
Poetics II (1984); Donald Keesey, "On Some Recent Interpretations of
Catharsis," The Classical World 72 (1979); Pedro Laín Entralgo,
The Therapy of the Word in Classical Antiquity (1970); Jonathan Lear, "Katharsis,"
Phronesis 33 (1988); Matthias Luserke, Die Aristotelische
Katharsis (1991); Richard P. McKeon, "Literary Criticism and the Concept
of Imitation in Antiquity," Critics and Criticism: Ancient and Modern
(ed. R. S. Crane, 1952); Martha C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness
(1986); Bennett Simon, Mind and Madness in Ancient Greece (1978);
Richard Sorabji, Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's
Theory (1980); Christian Wagner, "'Katharsis' in der aristotelischen
Tragödiendefinition," Grazer Beitråge 11 (1984).
|
|
Topics Index
Cross-references for this Guide entry: |
|
classical literature and theory,
hamartia, katharsis |
|
|
|
Copyright © 1997 The Johns Hopkins University Press.
All rights reserved. This document may be used, with this notice included,
for noncommercial purposes within a purchasing institution. No copies of
this work may be distributed electronically outside of the subscribed
institution, in whole or in part, without written
permission from
the JHU Press. |
|